to build in a clause for measure and guard processing
Parent topic: RULE-CLASSES Home
See rule-classes for a general discussion of rule classes and
how they are used to build rules from formulas. A :built-in-clause
rule can be built from any formula other than propositional
tautologies. Roughly speaking, the system uses the list of built-in
clauses as the first method of proof when attacking a new goal. Any
goal that is subsumed by a built in clause is proved ``silently.''
ACL2 maintains a set of ``built-in'' clauses that are used to
short-circuit certain theorem proving tasks. We discuss this at
length below. When a theorem is given the rule class
:built-in-clause
ACL2 flattens the implies
and and
structure of the
:
corollary
formula so as to obtain a set of formulas whose
conjunction is equivalent to the given corollary. It then converts
each of these to clausal form and adds each clause to the set of
built-in clauses.
For example, the following :
corollary
(regardless of the definition
of abl
)
(and (implies (and (true-listp x) (not (equal x nil))) (< (acl2-count (abl x)) (acl2-count x))) (implies (and (true-listp x) (not (equal nil x))) (< (acl2-count (abl x)) (acl2-count x))))will build in two clauses,
{(not (true-listp x)) (equal x nil) (< (acl2-count (abl x)) (acl2-count x))}and
{(not (true-listp x)) (equal nil x) (< (acl2-count (abl x)) (acl2-count x))}.We now give more background.
Recall that a clause is a set of terms, implicitly representing the
disjunction of the terms. Clause c1
is ``subsumed'' by clause c2
if
some instance of c2
is a subset c1
.
For example, let c1
be
{(not (consp l)) (equal a (car l)) (< (acl2-count (cdr l)) (acl2-count l))}.Then
c1
is subsumed by c2
, shown below,
{(not (consp x)) ; second term omitted here (< (acl2-count (cdr x)) (acl2-count x))}because we can instantiate
x
in c2
with l
to obtain a subset of
c1
.
Observe that c1
is the clausal form of
(implies (and (consp l) (not (equal a (car l)))) (< (acl2-count (cdr l)) (acl2-count l))),
c2
is the clausal form of
(implies (consp l) (< (acl2-count (cdr l)) (acl2-count l)))and the subsumption property just means that
c1
follows trivially
from c2
by instantiation.
The set of built-in clauses is just a set of known theorems in
clausal form. Any formula that is subsumed by a built-in clause is
thus a theorem. If the set of built-in theorems is reasonably
small, this little theorem prover is fast. ACL2 uses the ``built-in
clause check'' in three places: at the entrance to the
general-purpose theorem prover, as a filter on the clauses generated
to prove the termination of recursively defun
'd functions and as a
filter on the clauses generated to verify the guards of a function.
The latter two uses are the ones that most often motivate an extension to the set of built-in clauses. Frequently a given formalization problem requires the definition of many functions which require virtually identical termination and/or guard proofs. These proofs can be short-circuited by extending the set of built-in clauses to contain the most general forms of the clauses generated by the definitional schemes in use.
The attentive user might have noticed that there are some recursive
schemes, e.g., recursion by cdr
after testing consp
, that ACL2 just
seems to ``know'' are ok, while for others it generates measure
clauses to prove. Actually, it always generates measure clauses but
then filters out any that pass the built-in clause check. When ACL2
is initialized, the clause justifying cdr
recursion after a consp
test is added to the set of built-in clauses. (That clause is c2
above.)
Note that only a subsumptin check is made; no rewriting or
simplification is done. Thus, if we want the system to ``know''
that cdr
recursion is ok after a negative atom
test (which, by the
definition of atom
, is the same as a consp
test), we have to build
in a second clause. The subsumption algorithm does not ``know''
about commutative functions. Thus, for predictability, we have
built in commuted versions of each clause involving commutative
functions. For example, we build in both
{(not (integerp x)) (< 0 x) (= x 0) (< (acl2-count (+ -1 x)) (acl2-count x))}and the commuted version
{(not (integerp x)) (< 0 x) (= 0 x) (< (acl2-count (+ -1 x)) (acl2-count x))}so that the user need not worry whether to write
(= x 0)
or (= 0 x)
in definitions.
:built-in-clause
rules added by the user can be enabled and
disabled.
make a rule used by the typing mechanism
Parent topic: RULE-CLASSES Home
See rule-classes for a general discussion of rule classes and
how they are used to build rules from formulas. An example
:
corollary
formula from which a :compound-recognizer
rule might be
built is:
Example: (implies (alistp x) When (alistp x) is assumed true, (true-listp x)) add the additional hypothesis that x is of primitive type true-listp.whereGeneral Forms: (implies (fn x) concl) (implies (not (fn x)) concl) (and (implies (fn x) concl1) (implies (not (fn x)) concl2)) (iff (fn x) concl) (equal (fn x) concl)
fn
is a Boolean valued function of one argument, x
is a
variable symbol, and the system can deduce some restriction on the
primitive type of x
from the assumption that concl
holds. The third
restriction is vague but one way to understand it is to weaken it a
little to ``and concl
is a non-tautological conjunction or
disjunction of the primitive type recognizers listed below.''The primitive ACL2 types and a suitable primitive recognizing expression for each are listed below.
type suitable primitive recognizerThus, a suitablezero (equal x 0) negative integers (and (integerp x) (< x 0)) positive integers (and (integerp x) (> x 0)) negative ratio (and (rationalp x) (not (integerp x)) (< x 0)) positive ratio (and (rationalp x) (not (integerp x)) (> x 0)) complex rational (complex-rationalp x) nil (equal x nil) t (equal x t) other symbols (and (symbolp x) (not (equal x nil)) (not (equal x t))) proper conses (and (consp x) (true-listp x)) improper conses (and (consp x) (not (true-listp x))) strings (stringp x) characters (characterp x)
concl
to recognize the naturals would be
(or (equal x 0) (and (integerp x) (> x 0)))
but it turns out that we
also permit (and (integerp x) (>= x 0))
. Similarly, the true-lists
could be specified by
(or (equal x nil) (and (consp x) (true-listp x)))but we in fact allow
(true-listp x)
. When time permits we will
document more fully what is allowed or implement a macro that
permits direct specification of the desired type in terms of the
primitives.
There are essentially four forms of :compound-recognizer
rules, the
last two general forms above being equivalent. We explain how such
rules are used by considering the individual forms.
Consider a rule of the first form, (implies (fn x) concl)
. The
effect of such a rule is that when the rewriter assumes (fn x)
true,
as it would while diving through (if (fn x) xxx ...)
to rewrite xxx
,
it restricts the type of x
as specified by concl
. However, when
assuming (fn x)
false, as necessary in (if (fn x) ... xxx)
, the rule
permits no additional assumptions about the type of x
. For example,
if fn
is primep
, i.e., the predicate that recognizes prime numbers,
then (implies (primep x) (and (integerp x) (>= x 0)))
is a compound
recognizer rule of the first form. When (primep x)
is assumed true,
the rewriter gains the additional information that x
is a natural
number. When (primep x)
is assumed false, no additional information
is gained -- since x
may be a non-prime natural or may not even be a
natural.
The second general form addresses itself to the symmetric case, when
assuming (fn x)
false permits type restrictions on x
but assuming
(fn x)
true permits no such restrictions. For example, if we
defined exprp
to be the recognizer for well-formed expressions for
some language in which all symbols, numbers, character objects and
strings were well-formed -- e.g., the well-formedness rules only put
restrictions on expressions represented by consp
s -- then the
theorem (implies (not (exprp x)) (consp x))
is a rule of the second
form. Assuming (exprp x)
true tells us nothing about the type of x
;
assuming it false tells us x
is a consp
.
The third general form addresses itself to the case where one type
may be deduced from (fn x)
and a generally unrelated type may be
deduced from its negation. If we modified the expression recognizer
above so that character objects are illegal, then a rule of the
third form is
(and (implies (exprp x) (not (characterp x))) (implies (not (exprp x)) (or (consp x) (characterp x)))).Finally, rules of the fourth class address the case where
fn
recognizes all and only the objects whose type is described. In
this case, fn
is really just a new name for some ``compound
recognizers.'' The classic example is (booleanp x)
, which is just a
handy combination of two primitive types:
(iff (booleanp x) (or (equal x t) (equal x nil))).
Often it is best to disable fn
after proving that it is a compound
recognizer, since (fn x)
will not be recognized as a compound
recognizer once it has been expanded.
Every time you prove a new compound recognizer rule about fn
it
overrides all previously proved compound recognizer rules about fn
.
Thus, if you want to establish the type implied by (fn x)
and you
want to establish the type implied by (not (fn x))
, you must prove a
compound recognizer rule of the third or fourth forms. Proving a
rule of the first form followed by one of the second only leaves the
second fact in the data base.
Compound recognizer rules can be disabled with the effect that older
rules about fn
, if any, are exposed.
If you prove multiple compound recognizer rules for a function, you may see a warning message to the effect that the new rule is not as ``restrictive'' as the old. That is, the new rules do not give the rewriter strictly more type information than it already had. The new rule is stored anyway, overriding the old, if enabled. You may be playing subtle games with enabling or rewriting. But two other interpretions are more likely, we think. One is that you have forgotten about an earlier rule and should merely print it out to make sure it says what you know and then forget your new rule. The other is that you meant to give the system more information and the system has simply been unable to extract the intended type information from the term you placed in the conclusion of the new rule. Given our lack of specificity in saying how type information is extracted from rules, you can hardly blame yourself for this problem. Sorry. If you suspect you've been burned this way, you should rephrase the new rule in terms of the primitive recognizing expressions above and see if the warning is still given. It would also be helpful to let us see your example so we can consider it as we redesign this stuff.
Compound recognizer rules are similar to :
forward-chaining
rules in
that the system deduces new information from the act of assuming
something true or false. If a compound recognizer rule were stored
as a forward chaining rule it would have essentially the same effect
as described, when it has any effect at all. The important point is
that :
forward-chaining
rules, because of their more general and
expensive form, are used ``at the top level'' of the simplification
process: we forward chain from assumptions in the goal being proved.
But compound recognizer rules are built in at the bottom-most level
of the simplifier, where type reasoning is done.
All that said, compound recognizer rules are a rather fancy,
specialized mechanism. It may be more appropriate to create
:
forward-chaining
rules instead of :compound-recognizer
rules.
the relations to maintain while simplifying arguments
Parent topic: RULE-CLASSES Home
See rule-classes for a general discussion of rule classes and
how they are used to build rules from formulas. An example
:
corollary
formula from which a :congruence
rule might be built is:
Example: (implies (set-equal x y) (iff (memb e x) (memb e y))).Also see defcong and see equivalence.
General Form: (implies (equiv1 xk xk-equiv) (equiv2 (fn x1... xk ...xn) (fn x1... xk-equiv ...xn)))where
equiv1
and equiv2
are known equivalence relations, fn
is an
n-ary
function symbol and the xi
and xk-equiv
are all distinct
variables. The effect of such a rule is to record that the
equiv2
-equivalence of fn
-expressions can be maintained if, while
rewriting the kth
argument position, equiv1
-equivalence is
maintained. See equivalence for a general discussion of the
issues. We say that equiv2
, above, is the ``outside equivalence''
in the rule and equiv1
is the ``inside equivalence for the k
th
argument''
The macro form (defcong equiv1 equiv2 (fn x1 ... x1) k)
is an
abbreviation for a defthm
of rule-class :congruence
that attempts to
establish that equiv2
is maintained by maintaining equiv1
in fn
's
k
th argument. The defcong
macro automatically generates the general
formula shown above. See defcong.
The memb
example above tells us that (memb e x)
is propositionally
equivalent to (memb e y)
, provided x
and y
are set-equal
. The
outside equivalence is iff
and the inside equivalence for the second
argument is set-equal
. If we see a memb
expression in a
propositional context, e.g., as a literal of a clause or test of an
if
(but not, for example, as an argument to cons
), we can rewrite
its second argument maintaining set-equality
. For example, a rule
stating the commutativity of append
(modulo set-equality) could be
applied in this context. Since equality is a refinement of all
equivalence relations, all equality rules are always available.
See refinement.
All known :congruence
rules about a given outside equivalence and fn
can be used independently. That is, consider two :congruence
rules
with the same outside equivalence, equiv
, and about the same
function fn
. Suppose one says that equiv1
is the inside equivalence
for the first argument and the other says equiv2
is the inside
equivalence for the second argument. Then (fn a b)
is equiv
(fn a' b')
provided a
is equiv1
to a'
and b
is equiv2
to b'
. This is an easy consequence of the transitivity of
equiv
. It permits you to think independently about the inside
equivalences.
Furthermore, it is possible that more than one inside equivalence
for a given argument slot will maintain a given outside equivalence.
For example, (length a)
is equal to (length a')
if a
and a'
are
related either by list-equal
or by string-equal
. You may prove two
(or more) :congruence
rules for the same slot of a function. The
result is that the system uses a new, ``generated'' equivalence
relation for that slot with the result that rules of both (or all)
kinds are available while rewriting.
:congruence
rules can be disabled. For example, if you have two
different inside equivalences for a given argument position and you
find that the :
rewrite
rules for one are unexpectedly preventing the
application of the desired rule, you can disable the rule that
introduced the unwanted inside equivalence.
More will be written about this as we develop the techniques.
make a rule that acts like a function definition
Parent topic: RULE-CLASSES Home
Example: (implies (true-listp x) (equal (len x) (if (null x) 0 (if (null (cdr x)) 1 (len (cddr x))))))whereGeneral Form: (implies hyp (equiv (fn a1 ... an) body))
equiv
is an equivalence relation and fn
is a function symbol
other than if
, hide
or force
. Such rules allow ``alternative''
definitions of fn
to be proved as theorems but used as definitions.
These rules are not true ``definitions'' in the sense that they (a)
cannot introduce new function symbols and (b) do not have to be
terminating recursion schemes. They are just conditional rewrite
rules that are controlled the same way we control recursive
definitions. We call these ``definition rules'' or ``generalized
definitions''.
Consider the general form above. Generalized definitions are stored
among the :
rewrite
rules for the function ``defined,'' fn
above, but
the procedure for applying them is a little different. During
rewriting, instances of (fn a1 ... an)
are replaced by corresponding
instances of body
provided the hyp
s can be established as for a
:
rewrite
rule and the result of rewriting body
satisfies the
criteria for function expansion. There are two primary criteria,
either of which permits expansion. The first is that the
``recursive'' calls of fn
in the rewritten body have arguments that
already occur in the goal conjecture. The second is that the
``controlling'' arguments to fn
are simpler in the rewritten body.
The notions of ``recursive call'' and ``controllers'' are complicated by the provisions for mutually recursive definitions. Consider a ``clique'' of mutually recursive definitions. Then a ``recursive call'' is a call to any function defined in the clique and an argument is a ``controller'' if it is involved in the measure that decreases in all recursive calls. These notions are precisely defined by the definitional principle and do not necessarily make sense in the context of generalized definitional equations as implemented here.
But because the heuristics governing the use of generalized
definitions require these notions, it is generally up to the user to
specify which calls in body are to be considered recursive and what
the controlling arguments are. This information is specified in the
:clique
and :controller-alist
fields of the :definition
rule class.
The :clique
field is the list of function symbols to be considered
recursive calls of fn
. In the case of a non-recursive definition,
the :clique
field is empty; in a singly recursive definition, it
should consist of the singleton list containing fn
; otherwise it
should be a list of all of the functions in the mutually recursive
clique with this definition of fn
.
If the :clique
field is not provided it defaults to nil
if fn
does
not occur as a function symbol in body
and it defaults to the
singleton list containing fn
otherwise. Thus, :clique
must be
supplied by the user only when the generalized definition rule is to
be treated as one of several in a mutually recursive clique.
The :controller-alist
is an alist that maps each function symbol in
the :clique
to a mask specifying which arguments are considered
controllers. The mask for a given member of the clique, fn
, must be
a list of t
's and nil
's of length equal to the arity of fn
. A t
should be in each argument position that is considered a
``controller'' of the recursion. For a function admitted under the
principle of definition, an argument controls the recursion if it is
one of the arguments measured in the termination argument for the
function. But in generalized definition rules, the user is free to
designate any subset of the arguments as controllers. Failure to
choose wisely may result in the ``infinite expansion'' of
definitional rules but cannot render ACL2 unsound since the rule
being misused is a theorem.
If the :controller-alist
is omitted it can sometimes be defaulted
automatically by the system. If the :clique
is nil
, the
:controller-alist
defaults to nil
. If the :clique
is a singleton
containing fn
, the :controller-alist
defaults to the controller
alist computed by (defun fn args body)
. If the :clique
contains
more than one function, the user must supply the :controller-alist
specifying the controllers for each function in the clique. This is
necessary since the system cannot determine and thus cannot analyze
the other definitional equations to be included in the clique.
For example, suppose fn1
and fn2
have been defined one way and it is
desired to make ``alternative'' mutually recursive definitions
available to the rewriter. Then one would prove two theorems and
store each as a :definition
rule. These two theorems would exhibit
equations ``defining'' fn1
and fn2
in terms of each other. No
provision is here made for exhibiting these two equations as a
system of equations. One is proved and then the other. It just so
happens that the user intends them to be treated as mutually
recursive definitions. To achieve this end, both :definition
rules
should specify the :clique
(fn1 fn2)
and should specify a suitable
:controller-alist
. If, for example, the new definition of fn1
is
controlled by its first argument and the new definition of fn2
is
controlled by its second and third (and they each take three
arguments) then a suitable :controller-alist
would be
((fn1 t nil nil) (fn2 nil t t))
. The order of the pairs in the
alist is unimportant, but there must be a pair for each function in
the clique.
Inappropriate heuristic advice via :clique
and :controller-alist
can
cause ``infinite expansion'' of generalized definitions, but cannot
render ACL2 unsound.
Note that the actual definition of fn1
has the runic name
(:definition fn1)
. The runic name of the alternative definition is
(:definition lemma)
, where lemma
is the name given to the event that
created the generalized :definition
rule. This allows theories to
switch between various ``definitions'' of the functions.
The definitional principle, defun
, actually adds :definition
rules. Thus the handling of generalized definitions is exactly the
same as for ``real'' definitions because no distinction is made in
the implementation. Suppose (fn x y)
is defun
'd to be
body
. Note that defun
(or defuns
or mutual-recursion
)
can compute the clique for fn
from the syntactic presentation and
it can compute the controllers from the termination analysis.
Provided the definition is admissible, defun
adds the
:definition
rule (equal (fn x y) body)
. Thus, (fn a b)
will not be expanded unless (g a b)
can be established.
make a destructor elimination rule
Parent topic: RULE-CLASSES Home
See rule-classes for a general discussion of rule classes and
how they are used to build rules from formulas. An example
:
corollary
formula from which an :elim
rule might be built is:
Example: (implies (consp x) when (car v) or (cdr v) appears (equal (cons (car x) (cdr x)) in a conjecture, and v is a x)) variable, consider replacing v by (cons a b), for two new variables a and b.whereGeneral Form: (implies hyp (equal lhs x))
x
is a variable symbol and lhs
contains one or more terms
(called ``destructor terms'') of the form (fn v1 ... vn)
, where fn
is a function symbol and the vi
are distinct variable symbols, v1
,
..., vn
include all the variable symbols in the formula, no fn
occurs in lhs
in more than one destructor term, and all occurrences
of x
in lhs
are inside destructor terms.
To use an :elim
rule, the theorem prover waits until a conjecture
has been maximally simplified. If it then finds an instance of some
destructor term (fn v1 ... vn)
in the conjecture, where the instance
for x
is some variable symbol, vi
, it instantiates the :elim
formula
as indicated by the destructor term matched, splits the conjecture
into two goals, according to whether the instantiated hypothesis,
hyp
, holds, and in the case that it does, generalizes all the
instantiated destructor terms in the conjecture to new variables and
then replaces vi
in the conjecture by the generalized instantiated
lhs
.
At the moment, the best description of how ACL2 :elim
rules are used
may be found in the discussion of ``ELIM Rules,'' pp 247 of A
Computational Logic Handbook.
mark a relation as an equivalence relation
Parent topic: RULE-CLASSES Home
See rule-classes for a general discussion of rule classes and
how they are used to build rules from formulas. An example
:
corollary
formula from which a :equivalence
rule might be built is
as follows. (We assume that r-equal
has been defined.)
Example: (and (booleanp (r-equal x y)) (r-equal x x) (implies (r-equal x y) (r-equal y x)) (implies (and (r-equal x y) (r-equal y z)) (r-equal x z))).Also see defequiv.
General Form: (and (booleanp (equiv x y)) (equiv x x) (implies (equiv x y) (equiv y x)) (implies (and (equiv x y) (equiv y z)) (equiv x z)))except that the order of the conjuncts and terms and the choice of variable symbols is unimportant. The effect of such a rule is to identify
equiv
as an equivalence relation. Note that only Boolean
2-place function symbols can be treated as equivalence relations.
See congruence and see refinement for closely related
concepts.
The macro form (defequiv equiv)
is an abbreviation for a defthm
of
rule-class :equivalence
that establishes that equiv
is an
equivalence relation. It generates the formula shown above.
See defequiv.
When equiv
is marked as an equivalence relation, its reflexivity,
symmetry, and transitivity are built into the system in a deeper way
than via :
rewrite
rules. More importantly, after equiv
has been
shown to be an equivalence relation, lemmas about equiv
, e.g.,
(implies hyps (equiv lhs rhs)),when stored as
:
rewrite
rules, cause the system to rewrite certain
occurrences of (instances of) lhs
to (instances of) rhs
. Roughly
speaking, an occurrence of lhs
in the kth
argument of some
fn
-expression, (fn ... lhs' ...)
, can be rewritten to produce
(fn ... rhs' ...)
, provided the system ``knows'' that the value
of fn
is unaffected by equiv
-substitution in the kth
argument. Such knowledge is communicated to the system via
``congruence lemmas.''
For example, suppose that r-equal
is known to be an equivalence
relation. The :
congruence
lemma
(implies (r-equal s1 s2) (equal (fn s1 n) (fn s2 n)))informs the rewriter that, while rewriting the first argument of
fn
-expressions, it is permitted to use r-equal
rewrite-rules.
See congruence for details about :
congruence
lemmas.
Interestingly, congruence lemmas are automatically created when an
equivalence relation is stored, saying that either of the
equivalence relation's arguments may be replaced by an equivalent
argument. That is, if the equivalence relation is fn
, we store
congruence rules that state the following fact:
(implies (and (fn x1 y1) (fn x2 y2)) (iff (fn x1 x2) (fn y1 y2)))Another aspect of equivalence relations is that of ``refinement.'' We say
equiv1
``refines'' equiv2
iff (equiv1 x y)
implies
(equiv2 x y)
. :
refinement
rules permit you to establish such
connections between your equivalence relations. The value of
refinements is that if the system is trying to rewrite something
while maintaining equiv2
it is permitted to use as a :
rewrite
rule any refinement of equiv2
. Thus, if equiv1
is a
refinement of equiv2
and there are equiv1
rewrite-rules
available, they can be brought to bear while maintaining equiv2
.
See refinement.
The system initially has knowledge of two equivalence relations,
equality, denoted by the symbol equal
, and propositional
equivalence, denoted by iff
. Equal
is known to be a refinement of
all equivalence relations and to preserve equality across all
arguments of all functions.
Typically there are five steps involved in introducing and using a new equivalence relation, equiv.
More will be written about this as we develop the techniques. For now, here is an example that shows how to make use of equivalence relations in rewriting.(1) Define
equiv
,(2) prove the
:equivalence
lemma aboutequiv
,(3) prove the
:
congruence
lemmas that show whereequiv
can be used to maintain known relations,(4) prove the
:
refinement
lemmas that relateequiv
to known relations other than equal, and(5) develop the theory of conditional
:
rewrite
rules that drive equiv rewriting.
Among the theorems proved below is
(defthm insert-sort-is-id (perm (insert-sort x) x))Here
perm
is defined as usual with delete
and is proved to be an
equivalence relation and to be a congruence relation for cons
and
member
.Then we prove the lemma
(defthm insert-is-cons (perm (insert a x) (cons a x)))which you must think of as you would
(insert a x) = (cons a x)
.
Now prove (perm (insert-sort x) x)
. The base case is trivial. The
induction step is
(consp x) & (perm (insert-sort (cdr x)) (cdr x))Opening-> (perm (insert-sort x) x).
insert-sort
makes the conclusion be
(perm (insert (car x) (insert-sort (cdr x))) x).Then apply the induction hypothesis (rewriting
(insert-sort (cdr x))
to (cdr x)
), to make the conclusion be
(perm (insert (car x) (cdr x)) x)Then apply
insert-is-cons
to get (perm (cons (car x) (cdr x)) x)
.
But we know that (cons (car x) (cdr x))
is x
, so we get (perm x x)
which is trivial, since perm
is an equivalence relation.Here are the events.
(encapsulate ((lt (x y) t)) (local (defun lt (x y) (declare (ignore x y)) nil)) (defthm lt-non-symmetric (implies (lt x y) (not (lt y x)))))(defun insert (x lst) (cond ((atom lst) (list x)) ((lt x (car lst)) (cons x lst)) (t (cons (car lst) (insert x (cdr lst))))))
(defun insert-sort (lst) (cond ((atom lst) nil) (t (insert (car lst) (insert-sort (cdr lst))))))
(defun del (x lst) (cond ((atom lst) nil) ((equal x (car lst)) (cdr lst)) (t (cons (car lst) (del x (cdr lst))))))
(defun mem (x lst) (cond ((atom lst) nil) ((equal x (car lst)) t) (t (mem x (cdr lst)))))
(defun perm (lst1 lst2) (cond ((atom lst1) (atom lst2)) ((mem (car lst1) lst2) (perm (cdr lst1) (del (car lst1) lst2))) (t nil)))
(defthm perm-reflexive (perm x x))
(defthm perm-cons (implies (mem a x) (equal (perm x (cons a y)) (perm (del a x) y))) :hints (("Goal" :induct (perm x y))))
(defthm perm-symmetric (implies (perm x y) (perm y x)))
(defthm mem-del (implies (mem a (del b x)) (mem a x)))
(defthm perm-mem (implies (and (perm x y) (mem a x)) (mem a y)))
(defthm mem-del2 (implies (and (mem a x) (not (equal a b))) (mem a (del b x))))
(defthm comm-del (equal (del a (del b x)) (del b (del a x))))
(defthm perm-del (implies (perm x y) (perm (del a x) (del a y))))
(defthm perm-transitive (implies (and (perm x y) (perm y z)) (perm x z)))
(defequiv perm)
(in-theory (disable perm perm-reflexive perm-symmetric perm-transitive))
(defcong perm perm (cons x y) 2)
(defcong perm iff (mem x y) 2)
(defthm atom-perm (implies (not (consp x)) (perm x nil)) :rule-classes :forward-chaining :hints (("Goal" :in-theory (enable perm))))
(defthm insert-is-cons (perm (insert a x) (cons a x)))
(defthm insert-sort-is-id (perm (insert-sort x) x))
(defun app (x y) (if (consp x) (cons (car x) (app (cdr x) y)) y))
(defun rev (x) (if (consp x) (app (rev (cdr x)) (list (car x))) nil))
(defcong perm perm (app x y) 2)
(defthm app-cons (perm (app a (cons b c)) (cons b (app a c))))
(defthm app-commutes (perm (app a b) (app b a)))
(defcong perm perm (app x y) 1 :hints (("Goal" :induct (app y x))))
(defthm rev-is-id (perm (rev x) x))
(defun == (x y) (if (consp x) (if (consp y) (and (equal (car x) (car y)) (== (cdr x) (cdr y))) nil) (not (consp y))))
(defthm ==-symmetric (== x x))
(defthm ==-reflexive (implies (== x y) (== y x)))
(defequiv ==)
(in-theory (disable ==-symmetric ==-reflexive))
(defcong == == (cons x y) 2)
(defcong == iff (consp x) 1)
(defcong == == (app x y) 2)
(defcong == == (app x y) 1)
(defthm rev-rev (== (rev (rev x)) x))